One child: do we have a right to more?
Sarah Conly
Sarah Conly is an Associate Professor
of Philosophy at Bowdoin College, in Brunswick, Maine, USA. She is the author
of One Child: Do We Have a Right to More? (2016) and Against Autonomy:
Justifying Coercive Paternalism (2013)
sconly@bowdoin.edu
–––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––
DOI: 10.3197/jps.2016.1.1.27
Licensing: This article is Open Access (CC BY 4.0).
How to Cite:
Conly, S. 2016. 'One child: do we have a right to more?'. The Journal of Population and Sustainability 1(1): 27–34.
https://doi.org/10.3197/jps.2016.1.1.27
–––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––
We love our children, and for many of
us the time we spend with our children is the best part of our lives. The time
has come, though, to acknowledge that we need to have fewer of them, and that
indeed we don’t have a right to give birth to more than one.
The United Nations has predicted a
global population of 11.2 billion by the year 2100. They know, of course, that
the fertility rate – the number of children a woman has over her lifetime – has
dropped a great deal, to 2.5 per woman. Even so, given the high number of young
people who will themselves be having children, we still arrive at the
mind-boggling figure of 11.2 billion. If 2100 seems too far away to think
about, the prediction is 9.7 billion by 2050, well within the lifetime of many
of us (UN 2015).
No one who is familiar with these
facts doubts that such a growth in population will be a great danger, both to
humans and the environment at large. The question has been what to do about it.
Many people believe that while having more than one child per couple is
dangerous, the most we can do about this is plead for people to refrain. People
have a right to have as many children as they want, it is argued, and so there
is nothing we can actually do that might interfere with childbearing. Education
about the dangers of overpopulation is permissible, since education doesn’t
actually prevent people from doing what they want; in fact, it helps people do
what they want, since they can better see the effects of their actions.
Anything else would violate a fundamental human right, and it is morally wrong
to violate fundamental human rights, even when we think that would benefit
society at large. That’s why we don’t allow slavery, even if lots of people
would enjoy it: there are certain things you just can’t do to people, no matter
how much other people benefit from them.
In fact, however, having as many
children as you might happen to want isn’t a fundamental right. In my book, One
Child: Do We Have a Right to More? (2016), I argue that when you claim
something as a right you need to justify that claim, and you simply can’t
justify the claim that you have a right to have as many children as you want
when that will be as harmful to others as this much overpopulation is bound to
be.
We claim moral rights sometimes just
because we want something a lot, but wanting something and having a right to it
aren’t the same thing. People who study rights generally argue that there are
two possible justifications for claiming that you have a right to do something.
First, many people argue that if you absolutely have to have something in order
to have a chance at a decent human life, then you can claim that thing as a
right. For this reason, many people believe that we have a right to food,
because it’s impossible to live a decent life if we are starving. Now, having
food doesn’t guarantee a life of human happiness, but it gives you something no
one can be happy without. Other people argue that we have a right to education
for a similar reason – we might be contented even if we are completely
ignorant, but for one thing, that is less likely, and for another, even if we
are contented in a state of complete ignorance it seems less than a human life.
For a decent human life we need the basics for mental and physical health.
The fact that there is a justified
claim to food, though, doesn’t mean you can claim a diet of lobster, truffles,
and champagne, no matter how much you might prefer that. We have a right to
basic nourishment, what we need for a chance at satisfaction and good health,
not to whatever might most please us. Similarly for education: we think there
is a right to education, but that doesn’t mean that everyone has a right to go
to Harvard or Oxford, or a right to be maintained by others in the study of
particle physics for all of life. What you can claim from other people is
limited to what you need for a decent life, not for the life you would most
want.
Similarly for children. Some people
think that having a child is necessary for a decent life. I actually find this
unlikely, given the number of happy, flourishing, productive people we all know
of who are childless, but let’s say, for purposes of argument, that most people
need the experience of childbearing and childrearing to have a decent life. It
doesn’t follow from that that you have a right to as many children as you want,
any more than the right to food gives you a right to lobster and champagne. A
family with one child is just as much a family as a large family. Any parent
with one child experiences both the cares and rewards of childbearing and
childrearing. The fact that you would like more doesn’t mean you have a right
to more, any more than the fact that I would really like to work fewer hours
for the same salary I get now means I have a right to work fewer hours for the same
salary.
So, the fact that we can make
reasonable claims to have our own basic interests met doesn’t mean we can claim
a right to have as many children as we may happen to want. However, basic
interests aren’t the only thing that can justify a claim to a right. Often we
claim a more general right to live our lives as we want, to shape our lives in
line with our own values. Here, we say that respect for our autonomy as persons
gives us the right to do certain things. We say, for example, that we have a right
to freedom of speech, whether or not speaking freely makes us better off. Even
if our basic interests in food, education, etc. can be met without our having
access to these freedoms of self-expression, we feel these freedoms are morally
ours to claim. Indeed, we usually claim these rights even if what we want to do
is downright bad for us – the idea is that we should be allowed to craft a life
in accordance with our own values.
Do we then have a right to have as
many children as we want, arising from our general right to live autonomously?
Well, it depends. Right now we don’t.
The truth about these autonomy rights, these rights to choose to live your life
the way you want, is that which of these rights you have is always sensitive to
context. We say we have a right to free speech, but we also say you don’t have
the right to falsely yell ”Fire!” in a crowded theater.
John Stuart Mill, who wrote one of the most eloquent defenses
of freedom that we have, conceded that of course when and how you can
permissibly say something depends on how much harm that might do. We have a
general right to practice our religion, but if our religion required human
sacrifice, we obviously wouldn’t have a right to that. We often have a right to
do things that are somewhat harmful (saying mean things, for instance) but we
don’t have the right to do things that are devastatingly harmful. Right now,
having more than one child is just that: a world of 11.2 billion is a world of
climate change, water shortages, soil depletion, overcrowding, species
extinction, and many fear, insufficient food. It’s just too harmful to be
something we have a right to do.
But what can we do? One problem is
that we often don’t see how we can stop people from having too many children
for the planet to bear. The Chinese one- child policy famously led (at least
sometimes) to forced abortions and forced sterilizations, and people rightfully
see these as violating the right to bodily integrity. Even if you don’t have a
right to do something, if I can’t stop you without violating a right you do
have I’m not allowed to do that. If, say, the only way I can stop you from
trespassing through a distant corner of my field is to shoot you, I am not
allowed to shoot you, even though you have no right to trespass. So if there is
no morally permissible way to prevent people from having more than one child,
what is the point of talking about it?
Fortunately, there are morally
permissible ways to influence people’s childbearing practices. First, of
course, we do need education, as was mentioned above. Whatever else we do, we
will need to explain how the fact that the fertility rate has dropped does not
mean that we need not worry about population. Demographic momentum, the fact
that with so many young people replacing themselves the population will
continue to grow past, as far as we can tell, the breaking point, needs to be
explained. We need to teach, too, that so far we don’t see a technological fix
that will allow 11.2 billion people to live happily – many people seem sure that
we can easily produce lots of fresh water from sea water (not realizing how
much energy this takes), or that we can “fix” global warming despite our
continued increase in greenhouse emissions, or even that we can colonize other
planets to relieve the population burden. These things may perhaps be possible,
but we have no reason to think they are going to happen. Trusting in such
fanciful solutions would be like introducing your child to cigarettes on the
chance that someday we will know how to cure cancer – just plain irresponsible.
We need to teach that this isn’t something anyone has a right to do.
As I have said, though, education is
probably not enough. Habits are hard to change, and the habit of thinking of
something as harmless is particularly hard to get over. We’ve always celebrated
the birth of children, and the idea that it can be dangerous requires a real
conceptual shift, and we are very slow to do that. More is needed. We could,
for a start, cut down on the number of unplanned pregnancies. There is a huge
unmet need for contraception in the world, especially (not surprisingly!) in
some of the places with the highest fertility rates, such as Sub-Saharan
Africa. Women who would like to have fewer children aren’t able to, because
they have no way to control their own fertility. This is something the richer
countries of the world could help with, making universal access to family
planning facilities a priority. This would, honestly, be the right thing to do
even if overpopulation were not a danger.
However, the worst contributors to
greenhouse emissions are those of us in countries where contraception is
relatively easy to get. In these places more is needed than simply the ability
to have no more than one child. We need the desire. And here the government can
take important steps. We could, for example, give tax benefits to one-child
families. Alternatively, we could give tax penalties to those with more than
one. Or, we could change the expressive power of the message by simply saying
that we are fining those who have more than one child. We know that the number
of children people have is sensitive to finances – each economic depression and
recession sees a drop in the fertility rate, and each recovery sees a rise. And
the fact that the fertility rate has fallen as far as it has is probably due at
least in part to financial considerations – education and general childrearing
cost a fair amount of money, in most places, and may also require that a
two-income family become a one-income family, at least while the child is
small. There is good reason to think, then, that financial incentives and
disincentives would be enough to reduce the fertility rate. When a financial
disincentive is great enough to change our behavior
that may strike some as coercive, but again, the pressure here is to prevent us
from doing something we don’t actually have a right to do.
Would everyone be sensitive to such
pressures? Perhaps not, but we should bear in mind that sanctions for
undesirable activities are not generally designed to make those actions
literally impossible. We disapprove wholeheartedly of theft, and we punish it,
but we don’t do everything we possibly could to stop it. We don’t have cameras
that follow the activities of every citizen every second, because that would be
too intrusive. We don’t require that thieves have their hands cut off even if
that would persuade more people not to steal, because that would be too brutal.
We do what, combined with education and shared cultural values, will prevent
the vast majority of people from stealing. Similarly with children: we want to
reduce the fertility rate, but the fact that there are some who would rather
accept the sanction than refrain from having more than one child doesn’t mean
the policy has failed. It means it is like other public policies, where we
would like 100% compliance, but don’t expect to get it. We need enough to bring
about the requisite change.
Even if we have no right to more than
one child, is trying to prevent that a good idea? There are disadvantages to a
one-child policy, of course. It would involve personal losses. First and
foremost is simply that some people who want more children will be
disappointed. Secondly, it means that children would not have siblings. While
earlier beliefs that an only child would be predictably lonely and/ or spoiled
have been shown to be false, it may still be a loss not to have a sibling.
There are also ethical concerns: will a one-child policy lead to sex selection
in procreation of the sort that will lead to a society that is
disproportionately male? And then there are more material concerns: some ask
how an economy based on unending growth can succeed with a population that
isn’t constantly growing. If we adopt a one-child policy, the population will
fall. Eventually we will reach a sustainable number, and at that point, of
course, we would aim for stability, with an average of two children per couple,
or replacement value. Even then, though, our economy would have to run
differently. Our economy so far as been based on a
plan of infinite growth, and with a stable population rather than a growing
population our economy would need to function differently.
These are legitimate concerns.
However, none of them provides a sufficient reason to oppose a modern one-child
policy. To take the last first: it’s true, we don’t know how to run an economy
with a falling or stable population. At the same time, we don’t know how we are
going to run an economy with constant growth, either. A constant increase in
the use of resources just isn’t possible on a finite planet. It can’t happen –
we will simply run out of resources. Not everyone is happy with the economy as
it is working now, given the increasing inequality we see between rich and
poor, but even those who do think it functions well must admit that it just
can’t keep running the same way. We will simply run out of stuff. Given this, a
number of economists have suggested that we need to make a change – that we
need to figure out how to have satisfying lives that aren’t based on the
prospect of producing more and more things. No one wants a crashing economy,
but the way to avoid that isn’t just to keep doing what we have been doing.
Better to change now, while we still have fuel, water, food, and precious
minerals, than later.
Sex selection, too is something we
want to avoid. The evidence, though, is that sex selection is a phenomenon
distinct from falling fertility rates. People in the United States, Western
Europe, and the Far East have greatly reduced their fertility rates without
this resulting in any disproportion between boys and girls. And one of the
places that does show a clearly unnatural sex ratio is India, where people can
have as many children as they like. The cause of sex selection is, to make a
long story short, sexism. When women are not allowed to earn as much as men, or
are much more expensive to raise (if, say, they need unaffordable dowries for
marriage) they will naturally be the second choice for many people. This can
change, though, as we have seen. When women have equal standing, there is no
preference for boys.
The loss of the larger family one
might have wanted, and the loss of siblings, are real losses for some of us.
There will be parents who would be happier with more children, and children who
would be happier with siblings (as well as parents and children who wouldn’t be
any happier with more children). For some families, adoption may be possible,
but of course with a smaller number of children in the world this wouldn’t be
possible for everyone. I don’t think it can be denied that some people will be
worse off with fewer children in a family than they would be in a family with
more. Still, even if they have lost something of value, that haven’t lost as
much as would be lost in an overpopulated world. Small families are still
families, as said above, and bring the rewards of family life. The fact that
some people would have found a larger family more rewarding doesn’t mean they
need one for a happy or rewarding life. A life in which we lack food, or water,
or space, or any access to the natural world, is a not a decent life. And of
course a shortage of resources like these leads, typically, to conflict – civil
wars and international wars as people struggle for what they need. Having a
happy family in the midst of war is virtually impossible.
We need, then, to change our ways. We
need to recognize that those who have more than one child when they could do
otherwise are doing something they don’t have a right to do, and the
consequences will be disastrous.
References
Conly, S. (2013) Against Autonomy:
Justifying Coercive Paternalism. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Conly, S. (2016) One Child: Do We
Have a Right to More? Oxford, Oxford University Press.
United Nations, Department of
Economic and Social Affairs, Population Division (2015) World Population
Prospects: The 2015 Revision, Key Findings and Advance Tables. Working Paper
No. ESA/P/WP.241.